Blog

“The Truth about the Evidence Concerning Immortality”

366 3 31 Aug 2009

[This post continues the discussion of the last one.]

What is the evidence for or against:  (i) immortality is real, (ii) it’s false that it is real, (iii) eternal life is real, and (iv) it’s false that eternal life is real?

Let’s consider immortality in this post and eternal life in the next one.

Unless there’s evidence to the contrary, it’s always rational not to believe that something is real.  By way of analogy, in our legal system, the burden of proof is on the prosecutor, not on the defendant.  In other words, the prosecutor must prove that the defendant is guilty; the defendant does not have to prove a negative, that it’s false that he or she is guilty.

When it comes to the existence or nonexistence of something, the burden of proof is always on whoever makes the positive existential claim.  If you think that yeti are real and I disagree, in order to settle the dispute I don’t have to prove that it’s false that yeti exist; rather, you have to prove that they do exist.  This is because, unless one can demonstrate a contradiction (as can sometimes be done in logic or mathematics), it’s not possible to prove a negative existential claim.

If you are inclined to disagree, try to imagine how you would prove that, say, there are no yeti.  Since, if they were real, they would be perceivable objects, you would be required to have perceptual evidence of every place in the universe at one moment.  So, it’s impossible to prove that there are no yeti!  Naturally, then, the burden of proof falls on whoever thinks there are yeti.  Without a cadaver or other good evidence to the contrary, it’s rational to think that it’s false that they exist.

The concept of evidence is the chief concept in epistemology, much as the concept of reality (existence) is the chief concept in ontology and the concept of value is the chief concept in axiology.  So, like the concepts of reality and value, it is a fundamental concept.

It’s important to distinguish the two kinds of evidence, namely, demonstrative evidence and nondemonstrative evidence.

Demonstrative evidence yields knowledge.  Strictly speaking, we know something only when it is certain.  Butchvarov argues that knowledge is the unthinkability of mistake (see his THE CONCEPT OF KNOWLEDGE).  We know something if and only if we cannot even think of how we could be mistaken about it.  The domain of knowledge is limited; we can know some necessary (analytic) truths (for example, “red is a color” or “three is less than four”) and some truths about immediate experience (for example, “I have a headache”).  There’s no such thing as false knowledge.

All our other beliefs are in the domain of opinion.  Whereas there’s no such thing as false knowledge, there can be false opinion.  The evidence in favor of any opinion is nondemonstrative.  What is nondemonstrative evidence?  I don ‘t know.  Nobody else does either.  The chief problem in epistemology is figuring out what it is.  How can we tell the difference between a true opinion and a false one?  That’s a difficult nut to crack.

So it might seem, then, that either proposition about immortality is an opinion.  Not!

Here’s why.  Propositions must be intelligible to be true or false.  I don’t think that propositions about immortality are intelligible!  If so, they are neither true nor false.

What is it that is supposed to have immortal life?  What is it that is supposed to continue living beyond death?  Which subject is supposed to have immortality?

I have no idea.  At least for me, at this point the discussion loses sense!  I’m not bright enough to figure out what a nonbodily “soul” could be.  Though you may have one or believe you have one, I assure you that I am empty of such an entity.  I feel like someone born blind must feel when others are discussing colors.  I just don’t get it.  After a short while, I simply lose interest.

Notice, for example, that such a nonbodily soul could not be a something that perceives.  Therefore, too, it could not be something that imagines.  What would it do?  How could it be singled out (identified)?  There’s a good slogan in ontology:  “no entity without identity.”  Well, here, at least for me, there’s no identity and no entity.

Therefore, propositions about personal immortality are unintelligible and, so, neither true nor false.  Talk about them should be dismissed as something like confused wishful thinking.

As a matter of fact, and here’s the real stunner, propositions about separate persons are unintelligible and, so, neither truth nor false!  I intend to discuss this very important point in other posts.

In my next post I’ll discuss the evidence concerning eternal life.

“The Hidden Confusion About Immortality Exposed”

318 0 30 Aug 2009

Are you curious about immortality?

Observing a funeral always reminds me of the appalling ignorance concerning the distinction between immortal life [immortality] and eternal life.  Fortunately, ignorance is curable.

Since the prefix “im” negates what follows it, our topic is the opposite of mortal life.  It is life after death, or, if you prefer, life after life.  Therefore, it is not available now, during life.  It presupposes duration or continuance; in other words, it merely involves a longer time.  It’s the claim that there is a greater quantity to life than is initially apparent.

By way of contrast, eternal life is available now.  Eternal life is timelessness.  It has nothing to do with time; eternity is the opposite of temporality.  It’s qualitatively different.

This distinction yields four possibilities.  Neither is available to humans.  Both are available.  One is available, but the other isn’t.

Which of the four positions should we provisionally adopt?

Well, that depends upon the evidence.  Only now that the four possibilities are clearly distinguished does it make sense to inquire about which is best supported by evidence.  (I intend to talk about the evidence in my next post.  I shall commit myself to one of the four possibilities.)

It’s important, though, to distinguish what a claim is from the evidence regarding it.  For example, it’s senseless to argue for or against the existence of God without first becoming clear about the subject of the dispute, about what God is.  Otherwise, it’s impossible to determine which evidence is relevant.  Similarly, it’s senseless to try to think about immortality without clearly distinguishing it from eternal life.  Sadly and unnecessarily, that’s a distinction that is commonly overlooked.

Since these are important matters, it’s wise to insist on clarity.  Step one is becoming clear about what immortality is.  Step two is gathering and evaluating the relevant evidence.

“Life’s Momentum”

289 0 29 Aug 2009

Exactly one week ago I canoed on a river for the first time.

I’ve had considerable experience canoeing across northern lakes.  The proper canoes for that are 18 to 20 feet long with keels.  They are often heavily laden with camping equipment.  It’s usually hard work.  One must consider the wind, but lakes lack significant currents.

River canoes are shorter than lake canoes and have no keels.  Ours were lightly loaded.  As a result, they easily slipped sideways, which is a useful trait in white water.  Partly because it requires almost no paddling but only steering, river canoeing is fun.  The river’s current provides the momentum.

Did you ever wonder what provides the momentum in our lives?

Surely it’s our habits.  I like what Ed Foreman said about them:  “Good habits are hard to form, but easy to live with; bad habits are easy to form but hard to live with.”

What are the habits that lead to living wisely, excellently, well?

Does the quality of your habits accurately reflect the quality of your life?